Eternal preliminaries part 3, the problem of extending partial semigroups
In the previous post I have totally ignored my focus from the first post, namely that I want to focus on partial semigroups, not full semigroups. As mentioned in the first part this is not really a problem as any partial semigroup operation is in essence a restriction of a full semigroup operation. So the full semigroup is always a neat thing to fall back to when you’re in doubt. Nevertheless, if, as I claimed, it is an advantage to work with partial semigroups, can we not get around this problem?
Extending a partial operation to .
Luckily, it is very much possible to do extend a partial operation. (Un)fortunately, nobody’s perfect that is I don’t know how to get all the theory to run smoothly so in what follows I might have to fall back for some things. We’ll see.
So how do you extend the operation? Easy! Use the brute force method!
Extending the operation to
Ok, that’s a bit weird. The way I wrote it there is no reason to believe that such
First to note is: watch out! Maybe I’m trying to trick you with the definition, hiding behind the weirdness. As I wrote in the last post, the
- First, for semigroups we had defined
— this still seems to work fine, we’re just checking if some set is in . - But what kind of set are we checking? Going into detail, we find
— and this not clear at all! Remember, might not be defined. What do we do then? Do we want to include or exclude those incompatible ?
But, assuming you’re a forgiving reader, I think it still makes sense: just make
This is fine from the point of view of a full semigroup (since always
Again, with the analogous convention that
The most important observation
So after this short delay, we can say we have defined a partial operation on
- What can go wrong to prevent the multiplication from being defined?
- That is, which
actually yield an ultrafilter ? - In other words, how rich is the multiplication?
Luckily, this question can be answered rather easily. But let me begin with the most crucial observation and the goal of the rest of this post.
The semigroup
Kaboom! This is extremely nice. Even though our operation is partial, we get a relatively good piece of
The partial semigroup .
As the heading says, the nicest thing about this extension is that it yields a partial semigroup. This is positively surprising because strong associativity seems difficult to conserve. The key observation is the following.
Proposition For
This is a pretty natural observation. You’d expect the product to work out on the ultrafilters if they contain sets where the multiplication behaves nicely. This is, of course, a common phenomenon with ultrafilters: properties of an ultrafilter are often reflected by its elements and vice versa.
Proof.
- Like any good ultrafilter proof, we start with a partition:
. - Since
is an ultrafilter, one part is in . - If the second part is in
, then is not a filter, i.e., the forward direction of our equivalence holds by contraposition. - Assume
. - Since
is an ultrafilter, for any we get . - But then
, so is not a filter.
- Assume
- If the first part, call it
is in , then is an ultrafilter. - The only problematic case (i.e., the one deviating from the proof of the brute definition for full semigroups) is that
. - To see this realise that
since and each .
- To see this realise that
- The rest is straight forward and not really fulfilling.
- Closure under taking supersets and finite intersection is just as easy to check.
is prime. - Let
. - Now easily
. - Since
is prime, exactly one part is in . - In other words,
. - Since
is prime, exactly one part is in , say . - But this means by definition that
, as desired.
- Let
- The only problematic case (i.e., the one deviating from the proof of the brute definition for full semigroups) is that
And once again, I have taken the liberty of skipping a little bit ahead. In fact, I will spend the bigger part of the next post talking about other tricks like
But with this we can actually claim.
Theorem
The proof is long and rather boring. Using the previous proposition you can compare what it means for say
It’s almost midnight and I’m getting tired so let’s wrap up the proof of the supposedly important observation.
Proof that
- By the proposition, we know that the multiplication is defined for all
because contains all . (yeah, only – you can see some more general observations looming around, right?) - So the question is, whether the product is again in
. - But for that we just check that
by strong associativity. - So
for all , as desired.
Ok, after this small detour, we’re ready for some ancient and brilliant theorems. Ellis’s Lemma and Hindman’s Theorem coming right up.